GSI: Kuan
Hwa
08/10/2016
Diotima’s Argument in Plato’s
Symposium
Diotima’s account
of the pursuit of the Beautiful in Plato’s Symposium
translated by Benjamin Jowett is embedded within five textual layers:
Plato’s text contains a dialogue told by Apollodorus, who heard it from Aristodemus,
who heard from Socrates the content of a dialogue with his teacher Diotima. She
argues that if love is desire for what one lacks then highest form of love
attainable is the love of wisdom, which permits one to see the “science of
beauty everywhere.” While the force and coherence of Diotima’s account derives
from the schematic structure of her claims, the authority of her argument is authorized
only insofar as it allows Socrates to abstain from responsibility over the
claims it makes. As such, Diotima’s argument is a rhetorical device that
permits Socrates to advance claims on the nature of love without compromising the
Socratic paradox of “only knowing that one knows nothing.”
Diotima’s account
gives a clear outline of the successive stages one follow in the pursuit of love. In the trajectory the stages are described as directed “steps” from which one “mounts
upwards” or “ascends”. The language employed by Diotima emphasizes a vertical
structure where the attainability of each stage is a function of a linear
progression through a hierarchy of stages. This schema parallels the analogy of
beginning with “earthly” particular forms and ending with absolute “divine”
forms, as if gradually distancing from earth to heaven. It also parallels the
temporal structure of the beginning with the “youth” and ending with the
promise of “immortality.” Since the
schema begins with the love of “one form” and culminates to the love of “a single science” of love, from one to one,
the account feels self-contained and cyclical. As such, the account obeys
continuity of action, place, and time. This causal continuity between the onset
and the eventual goal of the trajectory on three parallel levels forms the
logical force of the account.
The linear ascent
from the particular to the general contrasts the notion of human cyclicality.
In the discussion of the immortal nature of love, Diotima says that man
undergoes “a perpetual process of loss and reparation—hair, flesh, bones,
blood.” By enumerating the components of the body, Diotima emphasizes the
disjunction of the physical body. The body is represented as if composed of
discrete parts, united in their evolution in unison. Absolute ideas, on the
other hand, are “not growing and decaying, or waxing and waning.” The division
between the mortal body and abstract absolute forms becomes the fundamental
dichotomy of the subjects of love, here defined to be desire for what one
lacks.
Diotima preempts
her explication of how one goes about pursuing that which one lacks by
presenting an analogous dichotomy between the categories of love. She
distinguishes between two categories: the “lesser mysteries” of the hierarchy
of love which “even you, Socrates, may enter” while “the greater and more
hidden ones… I know not whether you will be able to attain.” Diotima addresses
Socrates directly in the opening statement of the passage in a somewhat
disparaging tone when she says ‘even you’, where ‘you’ is immediately qualified
to be Socrates. By singling Socrates by name, Diotima identifies an individual
member of the category “mortals” captured by the premises of the popular
syllogism “Socrates is a man / all men are mortal.” This may be a show of
humility by Socrates’ himself, in contrast to the constant deification of
Alcibiades’ account depicting him in “divine and golden images of such
fascinating beauty.” Diotima’s tone emphasizes the asymmetry of her relationship
with Socrates, reminding present listeners that Socrates becomes a pupil in the
narrative while reinforcing her position as the guiding figure. As such,
Socrates is dissociated from the formulation of the present argument and
remains in the role of the messenger and loyal student disseminating Diotima’s
argument.
At first it seems
that Socrates is finally asserting a philosophical account after all the
dialectic dialogues we have studied where he merely contests and refutes the
interlocutor’s claims. Yet, the anecdotal (and putatively autobiographical) dialogue
with Diotima becomes evidence for how perplexity motivates the dialogue. When
Diotima asks Socrates “what is the manner of the pursuit” he deflects the
question by declaring his ignorance, “the reason why I came to you.” While
there is implicit praise in this response, Socrates’ careful avoidance of a
reply positions him as lacking experience or knowledge in the field and
justifies his interest in the conversation. First, this perhaps elicits the listener’s
empathy as it depicts younger Socrates as characteristically curious yet humble,
in contrast to his typical abrasiveness. The younger Socrates, victim of
material love for “gold, and garments, and fair boys” seems more human than the
“divine” and impenetrable teacher of Aristodemus’ narrative. Second, it posits
Socrates’ ignorance as the intellectual motive for the philosophical exploration,
paradoxical insofar as it suggests that the void of knowledge propagates
attaining knowledge.
However, Socrates
is careful to avoid explicitly claiming knowledge after retelling the dialogue.
During the dialogue, Socrates does not amplify or expound on Diotima’s claims. He
concludes by saying that these “were the words of Diotima; and I am persuaded
of their truth”. Again, the praise of Diotima’s wisdom conceals Socrates’
abstention from their claims. He emphasizes that these words are purely Diotima’s
and not his own; there is a division between the message and the messenger as
between the content of the words and their physical expression. It is important
that Socrates chooses to claim he is “persuaded” rather than “convinced” of the
truth. If persuasion is a manipulative rhetorical device, then Socrates again
resorts to the asymmetrical and manipulative relationship between speaker and
listener to suggest his impotence upon retelling the argument. This means
Socrates can still claim neutrality while advancing an argument on the
philosophical pursuit of knowledge that in turn serves the Platonic Theory of Forms,
unveiling the manipulations of two different levels of the text.
Works Cited
Plato, and Benjamin Jowett. Symposium.
Champaign, IL: Project Gutenberg, 2008.
1 comment:
Quinot,
Excellent précis! You thoroughly and lucidly map out Diotima's "encomium of love" as devised within an embedded mise en abîme. Your attention to the subtle nuances of Plato's recursive rhetoric and Socrates' supposedly sober account of Diotima indeed helps us understand and qualify the claims about the hierarchical scheme of the corporeal to the abstract.
Post a Comment